Keynote address presented at the conference, “Building Bridges for Wellness Through
Counseling and Psychotherapy,” Sampurna Montfort College, Bangalore, INDIA,
Disease Entity or Culture-Bound Syndrome? The Troubled History of DSM-IV’s Major Depressive Disorder Richard Noll, Ph.D. Associate Professor of Psychology DeSales University Center Valley, PA 18034-9568 richard.noll@desales.edu
The United States is currently gripped by a very controversial political campaign.
I am not speaking of the forthcoming election of a new president. Instead, I am speaking
of the political battles now being waged to change the content and the character of the
forthcoming 5th edition of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders,
which is scheduled to appear in print in 2012. The 4th edition of 1994, commonly referred
to as DSM-IV, has remained relatively unchanged since the appearance of the third
edition in 1980. Most historians of psychiatry regard the appearance of DSM-III some 28
years ago as a fundamental turning point in not only the history and practice of medicine,
but also as the engine of a profound cultural change. The new diagnostic classification
system and new nomenclature introduced in 1980 has not only framed scientific research
on mental disorders since that time; it has also significantly influenced the therapeutic
practice of psychiatrists, psychologists, counselors and other mental health professionals.
In the medical model, treatment rationally follows from diagnosis. The way in which
individual diagnoses are defined, therefore, also defines the type of distress a person is
suffering from and categorizes the person seeking help. Since 1980, the diagnosis of a
mental disorder has relied upon whether or not a person in distress meets a set number of
criteria in a list of signs and symptoms, many of which are often vague in nature.
However, since DSM-III, the diagnosis of a mental disorder does not depend on the
personal history of the patient nor the social, emotional, or economic context in which the
person’s distress arose. This dehistoricizing of the human life of an individual has led to a
cultural transformation in many Western countries with regard to the treatment of mental
disorders. Psychotherapy and counseling have been devalued as treatment modalities in
part, I believe, because the emphasis is on the personal narrative of the individual in
distress. Instead, since 1988, when Prozac was first widely prescribed in the United
States, there has been a general acceptance of treatments that rationally follow the
contextless and ahistorical DSM diagnostic entities. The social, emotional and economic
context of an individual’s life is largely irrelevant to most physicians who prescribe a pill
– only the disease entity itself matters. This is especially true for the large categories of
mental disorders that DSM classifies as Mood Disorders or Anxiety Disorders. Unlike the
Western treatment of traditional medical diseases, where a thorough history and objective
analyses of blood or urine samples, or imaging, can lead to a reliable diagnosis and
rational treatment, the current Western treatment of the most common mental disorder –
depression – relies on no objective physical tests and almost entirely disregards the
history of an individual. When a depressed person in the United States goes to his or her
general practitioner or family doctor – as most depressed persons do in America -- the
personal history of the patient is irrelevant. It does not matter if the person is depressed
because this is something that happens to them every winter whether their lives are good
or not, nor if the person has lost a job or ended a romantic relationship, nor if the person
is grieving the death of their father or their pet dog, the treatment is invariably the same:
pharmacological treatment with an antidepressant or anti-anxiety drug.
The political campaign to influence the ways in which the American Psychiatric
Association defines depression, bipolar disorder, and anxiety disorders in the next edition
of the DSM is not trivial. The stakes are high. In the United States a third to a half of all
patients coming in to see their general practitioner or family doctor are doing so because
of problems with depression and anxiety. Psychiatrists, psychologists, counselors, social
workers and other mental health professionals who work in clinics or in private practice
all report that a majority of their patients are seeking help because of problems related to
mood or anxiety. Pharmaceutical companies have received the highest profits in the
history of that industry through the introduction of a continual stream of newer (but not
necessarily better) antidepressants, mood stabilizers and anti-anxiety drugs since the age
of Prozac began in 1988. Millions in the Unites States receive disability payments from
the government for mental disorders, many of them for Major Depressive Disorder and
Bipolar I Disorder, and any alteration in the diagnostic criteria for specific syndromes in
the next DSM could affect their financial survival as well as their mental health. As I say,
the stakes are high. How the American Psychiatric Association defines mental disorders
such as depression will not only have a profound economic effect but will also directly
affect the individual lives of persons seeking treatment.
How the Western medical community defines depression is also of direct
relevance to the diagnosis and treatment of persons in non-Western societies. Since 1999
there has been an initiative to unify the diagnostic criteria of the American Psychiatric
association with the mental disorders listed in the International Classification of Diseases
of the World Health Organization. Since the ICD is more widely used in non-Western
societies, the importation of Western – indeed, essentially American – concepts of mental
health and mental disorder, and the fundamentally biological, molecular, and ahistorical
view of human nature itself which underlies it, will be a form of cognitive colonization
that must be assessed clearly and rationally. In India, for example, where seeking
treatment from psychiatrists, psychologists, counselors and other mental health specialists
is still not a widely accepted practice, will an unquestioned adoption of Western
diagnostic definitions of depression lead to a culture that demands – and expects – pills
instead of psychotherapy, counseling, or treatment by traditional Ayurvedic healers? Will
a more holistic and traditional view of human nature one day be replaced by Western
biological psychiatry’s view of human nature as exclusively biological and molecular?
According to the World Health Organization’s Global Burden of Disease study,
which was first published in 1996, by the year 2020 depression will be the number one
cause of disability across the world. This would of course include countries such as India.
Epidemiological studies in North America and Europe have found that the numbers of
people suffering from depression have risen markedly since the 1940s, and particularly
since the publication of DSM-III in 1980. Of course, the first question that must be asked
is: How exactly are we defining depression? And the second question is: Are we defining
depression correctly? As I say, the stakes are high – even for countries such as India.
Perhaps I should say, especially for countries such as India.
I would like to approach these issues from the perspective of history. I believe
that a perspective on how Western psychiatry has evolved its concepts of depression will
help us understand not only what is wrong with the current situation, but also what is
Depression is a creation of the 20th century. In the Western medical tradition,
what we now term depression has been part of the various clinical pictures of a mental
disorder the ancient Greeks called melancholia. The term melancholia was in wide use
until the early 20th century, disappeared from official psychiatry for most of the latter
two-thirds of the century, and now in the 21st century is being resurrected by some
prominent psychiatrists with the hope that it will reappear in DSM-V when it is published
Although signs and symptoms of depression were always at the core of
melancholia since ancient times, melancholia was a broad category of insanity that also
included many clinical phenomena that would today be defining characteristics of other
DSM mental disorders. Melancholia also included anxiety, obsessions, fixed ideas,
phobias, delusions, agitation, gastrointestinal problems, headaches, and other signs and
symptoms that are not part of the set of criteria for diagnosing a Major Depressive
episode or Major Depressive Disorder in DSM-IV. Also, for more than 2000 years
physicians recognized that melancholia could be categorized into two basic types. The
first consisted of forms of melancholia that seemed to be “uncaused” and afflicted the
person even during times in their lives when there were no traumas, stressors, or any
other negative life situations that might lead to such negative states of mind. The second
kind of melancholia consisted of forms of insanity that seemed to be directly “caused” as
a reaction to events in the life of the person. Although the numerous authors of medical
treatises differed widely on the subtypes and definitions of melancholia, they all tended to
agree on this basic division between types of melancholia that were endogenous and
seemingly uncaused and those that were seemingly reactive and caused by stresses or
It was only after the year 1886 that a few Western psychiatrists, primarily from
Germany, began advocating for the term depression or depressive states as a replacement
for the ancient term melancholia. In that year the Danish neurologist Carl Lange of
Copenhagen introduced the use of the term depression to describe a syndrome
recognizable to us today in the modern sense of the word. From later authors there was
also an increasing focus on the core symptoms of depression – low spirits, lack of
vitality, poor self esteem, fatigue, anhedonia, social withdrawal, excessive guilt, sleeping
and eating irregularities, preoccupation with death and negative thoughts, suicidal
ideation and even suicide attempts. The close connection of depression with anxiety was
also noted by the 1880s, as it is today.
A major turning point came in 1899 with the publication of the 6th edition of the
German psychiatrist Emil Kraepelin’s textbook, Psychiatrie. Although Kraepelin had
referred to “depressive states” in earlier edition of his book, the term depression was
enshrined in Western psychiatry with the introduction of the new term, manic-depressive insanity, which Kraepelin coined as a general, all-encompassing term for what we would
call all the Mood Disorders today. Kraepelin believed that all mood disorders (except one
– involutional melancholia) were expressions of one underlying disease entity. Because
Kraepelin’s major division of the insanities into manic-depressive illness and dementia
praecox (which constituted all of the psychotic disorders) was widely accepted into
American, British and German psychiatry, until 1980 anyone who suffered from
depression in its various forms would be labeled manic-depressive even if they did not
have a history of a manic episode in their past. With the publication of DSM-III in 1980,
manic-depressive illness disappeared as an official psychiatric diagnosis in the United
States and was split into two separate entities: Major Depression (in which a person
experiences one or more major depressive episodes) and Bipolar Disorder (in which a
person suffers from recurrent manic episodes as well as major depressive episodes, with a
manic episode being the trigger for the diagnosis). In the 21st century there is a political
movement among some prominent psychiatrists to revive the term manic-depressive
illness and return to Kraepelin’s idea that all mood disorders are really aspects of a single
underlying disease entity. There is also a movement underfoot to widen the definition of
what constitutes a mood disorder by identifying a whole host of new disorders that are
presumed to be part of a “bipolar spectrum.” I will return to this issue.
The use of the term depression in American psychiatry as a replacement for the
ancient term melancholia can be traced to a lecture given by the Swiss émigré Adolf
Meyer in New York in 1904. In that lecture Meyer strongly advocated dropping
melancholia and using the word depression instead. From that point on fewer and fewer
American psychiatrists referred to melancholia, although a few British psychiatrists, such
as Aubrey Lewis, continued using the term until well into the 1930s.
Meyer was the most influential psychiatrist in the United States from
approximately 1904 until his death in 1950. For most of his career he strongly resisted the
classification of mental disorders, claiming that too little was known about their nature to
even begin the process of classification. This was a perspective shared by the
psychoanalysts who began to influence American psychiatry in a perceptible way by
World War I, and who dominated the American Psychiatric Association from the late
1930s until the early 1980s. Another perspective shared by both Meyer and the Freudians
was the notion that most mental disorders were caused by the reaction to life experiences
and not by heredity or any primary underlying biological process. In Meyer’s “dynamic
psychiatry,” mental disorders were “reactions” or “reaction-types” that were caused by an
abnormal response to psychobiosocial stressors. Most cases of depression were largely a
reaction to the stresses of life, Meyer argued. The Freudians spoke of “depressive
neuroses” or other “psychoneuroses,” and they too placed the cause of depression in the
life experience and personal history of the individual. However, Adolf Meyer differed
with the Freudians on one essential point: Meyer believed that there were also cases of
depression which seemed to be autonomous or uncaused by any reaction to the stresses of
life. Some people seemed to sink into major depressive episodes without any apparent
cause, and did so sometimes even when they were most successful in life. Meyer believed
that this type of depression was probably biologically-based.
This distinction between two very different types of depression – one that was a
reaction to the stresses of life and the other that seemed to be biologically-caused – was
identified by every major Western psychiatrist in the 20th century except two: the British
psychiatrist Aubrey Lewis and the German psychiatrist Karl Leonhard, who both
believed there was only one type of depression. Despite this long history in psychiatry,
this distinction completely vanished with the publication of DSM-III in 1980. Instead, the
lines were blurred. The personal history of the individual no longer mattered. A person
could be suffering from a single episode of depression due to a recent loss, they could
have a history of multiple episodes of depression following major losses, chronic stress or
traumas in their lives, or they could have a history of major depressive episodes that
seemed to be unrelated to the events of their lives, and in some instances might be related
to the changing of the seasons. Since 1980, all of them would be given the same
diagnosis: Major Depression or, in DSM-IV terms, Major Depressive Disorder. The
context of the origin of the distress was regarded as irrelevant.
How did this happen? How did the American psychiatrists who created DSM-III
ignore 2000 years of observations that there were two fundamental types of depression,
caused and uncaused? To answer this question, I’ll review the political climate of
American psychiatry in the 1970s when DSM-III was being written.
From the 1940s until the early 1980s the psychiatrists on the faculties of medical
schools were mostly psychoanalysts or influenced by psychoanalysis. To most
Americans, psychoanalysis and psychiatry were synonymous during those decades. As I
have already mentioned, psychoanalysts in America were resistant and indeed largely
dismissive of attempts to classify mental disorders. As a group, they were generally
opposed to scientific research that investigated genetic or other biological hypotheses
regarding the causes and nature of mental disorders. Although two previous editions of
DSM had appeared – the first in 1952, heavily influenced by Meyer’s notion of “reaction-
types” and the second in 1968 which used mostly Freudian terminology – before 1980
very few psychiatrists actually used the diagnostic terms in the DSM. Incredibly, many
psychiatrists did not even own a copy of the diagnostic manual. They regarded diagnosis
as a mere formality that could be ignored.
There was only one psychiatric department in an American medical school that
did not have a single psychoanalyst on its staff – the medical school of Washington.
University of St. Louis. In the early 1970s a group of psychiatrists on that faculty who
were interested in exploring experimental psychiatric research devised Research
Diagnostic Criteria for each major mental disorder. The idea was to develop a set of
operational definitions of the major mental disorders that could be used by researchers
interested in exploring their biological and psychological basis. According to their logic,
if scientific studies were conducted using the same diagnostic criteria to identify subjects
for experiments, then findings across studies could be generalized. Psychiatric research
until that time was a mess – different criteria were used to identify subjects by different
researchers, and results across studies were difficult to interpret. The Washington
University group was joined by Robert Spitzer of New York, a psychoanalytically-trained
psychiatrist who had lost his Freudian faith. Since most of the members of the American
Psychiatric Association were psychoanalysts and had little interest in revising the DSM,
Robert Spitzer was approved to head the project for developing DSM-III and paid little
attention to what he and his colleagues were doing. Spitzer and his colleagues used the
Research Diagnostic Criteria developed in St. Louis as the basis for DSM-III. The idea
was to produce a manual with definitions of mental disorders that would be useful to
scientific researchers as well as clinicians. Spitzer single-handedly created many of the
mental disorders in that edition himself in order to appease various special interest groups
within the psychiatric community. By the time the membership of the American
Psychiatric Association learned of the fundamental change in the philosophy of the DSM
-- especially the elimination of almost all Freudian terms and any claim about the “cause”
of a mental disorder, whether as a reactive neurosis or something biological – it was too
late. DSM-III was published in 1980 and within a few years became the basis for
reimbursement for treatment by American insurance companies. By the mid 1980s,When
using an official DSM-III diagnosis determined whether a physician would be paid for
services or not, even the oldest psychoanalysts had to buy a copy of the book and actually
Because the creators of DSM-III strove to eliminate diagnosis based on presumed
cause – in part, as a reaction to the psychoanalysts and their emphasis on personal
experience as the cause of all mental disorders -- the boundary was blurred between the
two forms of depression. The context in which a person became depressed was lost, and
remains so today. This has had two profound effects in the past 28 years. First, the
number of persons diagnosed with a medical disorder known as Major Depression or
Dysthymia – the two major forms of depression in DSM – dramatically increased.
Whereas experiencing depression as a natural, normal reaction to a loss or a trauma was
seen as a part of life, now even those aspects of human existence became medicalized.
Even today, according to DSM-IV the depression that naturally follows the death of a
loved one that is part of normal grieving is only considered “normal” for two months
following the loss. After that, the grieving person is considered to be suffering from
Major Depressive Disorder – a medical condition akin to a disease process.
A second effect of the blurring of the boundaries of caused and uncaused
depression has been the confounds created in biological research on depression. The
purpose of biological research in psychiatry is to identify the biological substrates of
persons suffering from a specific mental disorder in order to understand the etiology and
pathophysiology of that disorder as well as to lead to the development of more effective
medications to treat it. However, as American sociologists Allan Horwitz and Jerome
Wakefield have recently argued in a book published last year, much of the hundreds of
millions of dollars used to fund research on the biology of depression since 1980 may
have been wasted due to the fact that these studies used the faulty DSM-III operational
definition of depression, which does not distinguish between caused and uncaused
depression. Horwitz and Wakefield compare the situation to an upside-down pyramid: the
tip of the pyramid rests on a single unstable point – the diagnostic criteria for major
depression in DSM-III. If the definition is faulty and does not distinguish well between
reactive and endogenous depressions, then the scientific research will be contradictory,
inconclusive, and filled with confounds. And indeed this has largely been the case for
In their influential 2007 book, The Loss of Sadness, Horwitz and Wakefield
outline the argument I have made above: that historically there have been two forms of
depression, caused and uncaused, and DSM has blurred the boundaries. However, they
further make the case for the return of the recognition on the part of Western psychiatrists
that sadness is a normal reaction to loss, and that the experience of loss is a part of the
human condition. Most sadness, in their view, is reversible with a change of life
conditions, or psychotherapy, and does not require a medical diagnosis or
Horwitz and Wakefield’s book has generated considerable attention in the
psychiatric community because it includes a foreword by Robert Spitzer – the prime
editor and author of DSM-III. Spitzer, as it turns out, has changed his mind. He now
understands the mess caused by DSM’s rejection of the context in which depression
arises. He admits that this mistake has poisoned the large scale epidemiological research
studies of depression, leading to the conclusion that it is more common than may really
be the case. Without doing so explicitly, Spitzer is implicitly criticizing the World Health
Organization’s claim that depression will be the number one cause of disability in the
world by the year 2020. He is also casting doubt on the vast amount of research into the
biology of depression. However, although he acknowledges that ignoring the context of a
person’s life that may give rise to depression was a mistake, he remains skeptical that a
ay could be found to incorporate this new perspective into DSM-V.
So what does the future hold? Melancholia may return to official American
psychiatry as the term for the “uncaused” and presumable biologically-based form of
depression. The Mood Disorders may very well return to Emil Kraepelin’s notion that
they are almost all aspects of a single underlying disorder that will be called manic-
dperessive illness once again or bipolar spectrum disorders. The definition of the Mood
Disorders will probably widen to include many forms of bipolar disorder that shade into
the normal fluctuations of mood, with almost no room left for identifying what “normal”
mood fluctuations may be. Indeed, the pharmaceutical industry has long been funding
researchers who promote this bipolar spectrum idea, in part to widen the number of
persons who can receive a diagnosis so that they can be prescribed medications for them.
The medicalization of human existence has reached deep into the lives of everyday
people in North America, and whereas 30 years ago most Americans and Canadians
would have been reluctant to seek out medication for sadness or anxiety, today they flock
to their general practitioners in massive numbers to gain access to the continuous stream
of new medications introduced every year for depression and anxiety.
I have approached the problem of depression from an historical perspective in the
hope that these shifting political views in American psychiatry might provide a context
for the critical evaluation of American concepts by those of you here in India who may be
unaware of these debates. I believe an awareness of the Western debates about what
constitutes depression will be of direct relevance to the students of Montfort College who
are now be trained to counsel persons in distress. I am also hoping to stimulate a
discussion that will enlighten me as the perspective of Indian psychiatry regarding the
References
Healy, D. Let Them Eat Prozac: The Unhealthy Relationship Between the Pharmaceutical Industry and Depression. New York: New York University Press, 2007.
Horwitz, A.V. and J.C. Wakefield. The Loss of Sadness: How Psychiatry Transformed Normal Sorrow into Depressive Disorder. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Rosenberg, C.E. Contested boundaries: Psychiatry, disease and diagnosis. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 49 (2006): 407-424.
Shorter, E. The doctrine of the two depressions in historical perspective. Acta Psychiactrica Scandinavica 115 (2007): 5-13.
Taylor, M.A., and M. Fink. Melancholia: The Diagnosis, Pathophysiology and Treatment of Depressive Illness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006.
Curriculum Vitae Laura Campanello , nata a Merate – LC- Il 30.07.1970 Cell: 339.1442609 Sito: www.cura-di-se.it e-mail: lauracampanello@yahoo.it Formazione: • luglio.‘89: Diploma di Scuola Sperimentale Magistrale Ist. Greppi Monticello B. –CO- • maggio ‘96: Diploma di Laurea in Filosofia - indirizzo: Psicologia – (Univ. Statale Milano) • Dicembre 2004: Diploma di Laur
Onco type DX , developed by Genomic Health, is a diagnostic test that quantifies the likelihood of disease recurrence in women with early-stage hormone estrogen receptor (ER) positive only ( prognostic significance) and assesses the likely benefit from certain types of ( predictive significance). Onco type DX analyzes a panel of 21 genes within a tumor to determine a Recurrence Sco